Jump to content

Measurable cardinal

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure on a cardinal κ, or more generally on any set. For a cardinal κ, it can be described as a subdivision of all of its subsets into large and small sets such that κ itself is large, ∅ and all singletons {α} (with α ∈ κ) are small, complements of small sets are large and vice versa. The intersection of fewer than κ large sets is again large.[1]

It turns out that uncountable cardinals endowed with a two-valued measure are large cardinals whose existence cannot be proved from ZFC.[2]

The concept of a measurable cardinal was introduced by Stanisław Ulam in 1930.[3]

Definition

[edit]

Formally, a measurable cardinal is an uncountable cardinal number κ such that there exists a κ-additive, non-trivial, 0-1-valued measure μ on the power set of κ.

Here, κ-additive means: For every λ < κ and every λ-sized set {Aβ}β<λ of pairwise disjoint subsets Aβ ⊆ κ, we have

μ(⋃β<λ Aβ) = Σβ<λ μ(Aβ).

Equivalently, κ is a measurable cardinal if and only if it is an uncountable cardinal with a κ-complete, non-principal ultrafilter. This means that the intersection of any strictly less than κ-many sets in the ultrafilter, is also in the ultrafilter.

Equivalently, κ is measurable means that it is the critical point of a non-trivial elementary embedding of the universe V into a transitive class M. This equivalence is due to Jerome Keisler and Dana Scott, and uses the ultrapower construction from model theory. Since V is a proper class, a technical problem that is not usually present when considering ultrapowers needs to be addressed, by what is now called Scott's trick.

Properties

[edit]

It is trivial to note that if κ admits a non-trivial κ-additive measure, then κ must be regular. (By non-triviality and κ-additivity, any subset of cardinality less than κ must have measure 0, and then by κ-additivity again, this means that the entire set must not be a union of fewer than κ sets of cardinality less than κ.) Finally, if λ < κ, then it can't be the case that κ ≤ 2λ. If this were the case, we could identify κ with some collection of 0-1 sequences of length λ. For each position in the sequence, either the subset of sequences with 1 in that position or the subset with 0 in that position would have to have measure 1. The intersection of these λ-many measure 1 subsets would thus also have to have measure 1, but it would contain exactly one sequence, which would contradict the non-triviality of the measure. Thus, assuming the Axiom of Choice, we can infer that κ is a strong limit cardinal, which completes the proof of its inaccessibility.

Although it follows from ZFC that every measurable cardinal is inaccessible (and is ineffable, Ramsey, etc.), it is consistent with ZF that a measurable cardinal can be a successor cardinal. It follows from ZF + AD that ω1 is measurable,[4] and that every subset of ω1 contains or is disjoint from a closed and unbounded subset.

Ulam showed that the smallest cardinal κ that admits a non-trivial countably-additive two-valued measure must in fact admit a κ-additive measure. (If there were some collection of fewer than κ measure-0 subsets whose union was κ, then the induced measure on this collection would be a counterexample to the minimality of κ.) From there, one can prove (with the Axiom of Choice) that the least such cardinal must be inaccessible.

If κ is measurable and p ∈ Vκ and M (the ultrapower of V) satisfies ψ(κ, p), then the set of α < κ such that V satisfies ψ(α, p) is stationary in κ (actually a set of measure 1). In particular if ψ is a Π1 formula and V satisfies ψ(κ, p), then M satisfies it and thus V satisfies ψ(α, p) for a stationary set of α < κ. This property can be used to show that κ is a limit of most types of large cardinals that are weaker than measurable. Notice that the ultrafilter or measure witnessing that κ is measurable cannot be in M since the smallest such measurable cardinal would have to have another such below it, which is impossible.

If one starts with an elementary embedding j1 of V into M1 with critical point κ, then one can define an ultrafilter U on κ as { S ⊆ κ | κ ∈ j1(S) }. Then taking an ultrapower of V over U we can get another elementary embedding j2 of V into M2. However, it is important to remember that j2 ≠ j1. Thus other types of large cardinals such as strong cardinals may also be measurable, but not using the same embedding. It can be shown that a strong cardinal κ is measurable and also has κ-many measurable cardinals below it.

Every measurable cardinal κ is a 0-huge cardinal because κM ⊆ M, that is, every function from κ to M is in M. Consequently, Vκ+1 ⊆ M.

Implications of existence

[edit]

If a measurable cardinal exists, every Σ1
2
(with respect to the analytical hierarchy) set of reals has a Lebesgue measure.[4] In particular, any non-measurable set of reals must not be Σ1
2
.

Real-valued measurable

[edit]

A cardinal κ is called real-valued measurable if there is a κ-additive probability measure on the power set of κ that vanishes on singletons. Real-valued measurable cardinals were introduced by Stefan Banach (1930). Banach & Kuratowski (1929) showed that the continuum hypothesis implies that 𝔠 is not real-valued measurable. Stanislaw Ulam (1930) showed (see below for parts of Ulam's proof) that real valued measurable cardinals are weakly inaccessible (they are in fact weakly Mahlo). All measurable cardinals are real-valued measurable, and a real-valued measurable cardinal κ is measurable if and only if κ is greater than 𝔠. Thus a cardinal is measurable if and only if it is real-valued measurable and strongly inaccessible. A real valued measurable cardinal less than or equal to 𝔠 exists if and only if there is a countably additive extension of the Lebesgue measure to all sets of real numbers if and only if there is an atomless probability measure on the power set of some non-empty set.

Solovay (1971) showed that existence of measurable cardinals in ZFC, real-valued measurable cardinals in ZFC, and measurable cardinals in ZF, are equiconsistent.

Weak inaccessibility of real-valued measurable cardinals

[edit]

Say that a cardinal number α is an Ulam number if[5][nb 1]

whenever

then

if |X| ≤ α then μ(X) = 0.

Equivalently, a cardinal number α is an Ulam number if

whenever

  1. ν is an outer measure on a set Y, and F a set of pairwise disjoint subsets of Y,
  2. ν(⋃F) < ∞,
  3. ν(A) = 0 for AF,
  4. G is ν-measurable for every G ⊂ F,

then

if |F| ≤ α then ν(⋃F) = 0.

The smallest infinite cardinal 0 is an Ulam number. The class of Ulam numbers is closed under the cardinal successor operation.[6] If an infinite cardinal β has an immediate predecessor α that is an Ulam number, assume μ satisfies properties (1)–(4) with X = β. In the von Neumann model of ordinals and cardinals, for each x ∈ β, choose an injective function

fx: xα

and define the sets

U(b, a) = { x ∈ β | fx(b) = a }

Since the fx are one-to-one, the sets

U(b, a) | b ∈ β } with a ∈ α fixed
U(b, a) | a ∈ α } with b ∈ β fixed

are pairwise disjoint. By property (2) of μ, the set

b ∈ β | μ(U(b, a)) > 0 }

is countable, and hence

|{ (b, a) ∈ β × α | μ(U(b, a)) > 0 }| ≤ ℵ0α.

Thus there is a b0 such that

μ(U(b0, a)) = 0 for every a ∈ α

implying, since α is an Ulam number and using the second definition (with ν = μ and conditions (1)–(4) fulfilled),

μ(⋃aα U(b0, a)) = 0.

If b0 < x < β and fx(b0) = ax then x ∈ U(b0, ax). Thus

β = b0 ∪ {b0} ∪ ⋃aα U(b0, a)

By property (2), μ({b0}) = 0, and since |b0| ≤ α, by (4), (2) and (3), μ(b0) = 0. It follows that μ(β) = 0. The conclusion is that β is an Ulam number.

There is a similar proof[7] that the supremum of a set S of Ulam numbers with |S| an Ulam number is again a Ulam number. Together with the previous result, this implies that a cardinal that is not an Ulam number is weakly inaccessible.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ The notion in the article Ulam number is different.

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^ Maddy 1988
  2. ^ Jech 2002
  3. ^ Ulam 1930
  4. ^ a b T. Jech, "The Brave New World of Determinacy" (PDF download). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 5, number 3, November 1981 (pp.339--349).
  5. ^ Federer 1996, Section 2.1.6
  6. ^ Federer 1996, Second part of theorem in section 2.1.6.
  7. ^ Federer 1996, First part of theorem in section 2.1.6.

References

[edit]
  • Banach, Stefan (1930), "Über additive Maßfunktionen in abstrakten Mengen", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 15: 97–101, doi:10.4064/fm-15-1-97-101, ISSN 0016-2736.
  • Banach, Stefan; Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1929), "Sur une généralisation du probleme de la mesure", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 14: 127–131, doi:10.4064/fm-14-1-127-131, ISSN 0016-2736.
  • Drake, F. R. (1974), Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; V. 76), Elsevier Science Ltd, ISBN 978-0-7204-2279-5.
  • Federer, H. (1996) [1969], Geometric Measure Theory, Classics in Mathematics (1st ed reprint ed.), Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer Verlag, ISBN 978-3540606567.
  • Jech, Thomas (2002), Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded), Springer, ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
  • Kanamori, Akihiro (2003), The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings (2nd ed.), Springer, ISBN 3-540-00384-3.
  • Maddy, Penelope (1988), "Believing the Axioms. II", The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 53 (3): 736–764, doi:10.2307/2274569, JSTOR 2274569, S2CID 16544090. A copy of parts I and II of this article with corrections is available at the author's web page.
  • Solovay, Robert M. (1971), "Real-valued measurable cardinals", Axiomatic set theory (Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., Vol. XIII, Part I, Univ. California, Los Angeles, Calif., 1967), Providence, R.I.: Amer. Math. Soc., pp. 397–428, MR 0290961.
  • Ulam, Stanislaw (1930), "Zur Masstheorie in der allgemeinen Mengenlehre", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16: 140–150, doi:10.4064/fm-16-1-140-150, ISSN 0016-2736.